Loading
Loading

Chapter 4 - The Legal Theory of Animal Rights

  1. Introduction
  • For a supplementary perspective, arguing that advocacy centred on the duties of humans to animals rather than the rights of animals would focus discussion, more appropriately, on the oppressive conduct of humans and related justifications, see: Taimie L Bryant, ‘Animals Unmodified: Defining Animals/Defining Human Obligations to Animals’ [2006] University of Chicago Legal Forum 137, available at https://chicagounbound.uchicago.edu/uclf/vol2006/iss1/6/. For a similar argument about rights-discourse being impoverished politically, see: Rüdiger Bittner, ‘On Invoking Human Rights When There Aren’t Any’ in Susanne Kaul and David Kim (eds), Imagining human rights (De Gruyter 2015), available at https://doi.org/10.1515/9783110376616-006
  • For a reflection on the nature of rights theories, see: Alon Harel, ‘Theories of Rights’ in Martin P Golding and William A Edmundson (eds), The Blackwell guide to the philosophy of law and legal theory (Blackwell 2008), available at https://doi.org/10.1002/9780470690116.ch13
  • For a supplementary perspective on legal rights-holding and/or legal personhood as a political boundary problem, see: Elias L Khalil, ‘What Determines the Boundary of Civil Society? Hume, Smith and the Justification of European Exploitation of Non-Europeans’ (2013) 60 Theoria 26, available at https://www.jstor.org/stable/42705247
  1. Are Animals Fit to Have Legal Rights?
  • For an elaboration on and defense of Raz’s interest theory approach to legal rights, see: Aleardo Zanghellini, ‘Raz on Rights: Human Rights, Fundamental Rights, and Balancing’ (2017) 30 Ratio Juris 25, available at https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9337.2011.00502.x
  • For a critique of the critique of rights inflation, as denigrating new claims for justice, see: Jens T Theilen, ‘The Inflation of Human Rights: A Deconstruction’ (2021) 34 Leiden Journal of International Law 831, available at https://doi.org/10.1017/S0922156521000297
  • For an argument that intrinsic value can be based on an entity’s instrumental value, see: Shelly Kagan, ‘Rethinking Intrinsic Value’ (1998) 2 The Journal of Ethics 277, available at https://www.jstor.org/stable/25115588
  1. Do Animals Already Have Legal Rights?
  • For an argument that applies Hohfeld’s framework to argue that animals currently have legal rights in a specific jurisdiction—South Africa—see: David Bilchitz, ‘Moving Beyond Arbitrariness: The Legal Personhood And Dignity Of Non-Human Animals’ (2009) 25 South African Journal on Human Rights 38, available at https://www.tandfonline.com/doi/abs/10.1080/19962126.2009.11865192
  1. Would Animals Need to Become Legal Persons?
  • For a short reflection on Naffine’s work that considers the implications of extending legal personhood to animals, see: Steven Tudor, ‘Some Implications for Legal Personhood of Extending Legal Rights to Non-Human Animals’ (2010) 35 Australian Journal of Legal Philosophy 134, available at http://www.austlii.edu.au/au/journals/AUJlLawPhil/2010/13.pdf
  • For a consideration of how the legal status of animals is changing (or de-objectification), with comments on legal personhood as a future development, see: Pablo Lerner, ‘Animals Are Not Objects but Are Not Yet Subjects: Developments in the Proprietary Status of Animals’ (2022) 18 Animal & Natural Resource Law Review 267, available at https://ssrn.com/abstract=4251828
  • For an analytical discussion of the nature of legal personhood, see: Tomasz Pietrzykowski, ‘What Is Legal Personhood?’, Personhood Beyond Humanism: Animals, Chimeras, Autonomous Agents and the Law (1st ed. 2018, Springer International Publishing: Imprint: Springer 2018), available at https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-78881-4_2
  • For the idea that legal personhood functions as the “right to have rights” (a phrase coined by Hannah Arendt) in line with the Traditional View of personhood and the thick conception of legal rights, see: Raffael N Fasel, ‘The Leo and Hercules Trial: An Historic Step for Animal Rights or Business as Usual?’ (GBS schweiz, 26 May 2015), available at https://gbs-schweiz.org/blog/legal-personhood-and-rights/index.html
  • For an argument about the socio-political conditions that must be in place for a foundational, Arendtian right to have rights to be meaningful, see: James D Ingram, ‘What Is a “Right to Have Rights”? Three Images of the Politics of Human Rights’ (2008) 102 The American Political Science Review 401, available at https://www.jstor.org/stable/27644535
  • For a short but recent restatement by Francione of his key views, see: Gary L Francione, ‘Some Brief Comments on Animal Rights’ (2020) 10 Animal Frontiers 29, available at https://doi.org/10.1093/af/vfz050
  • For reviews of Wise’s theory, see: Daniel Davison-Vecchione and Kate Pambos, ‘Steven M. Wise and the Common Law Case for Animal Rights: Full Steam Ahead’ (2017) 30 Canadian Journal of Law & Jurisprudence 387, available at https://doi.org/10.1017/cjlj.2017.14 and Robert RM Verchick, ‘A New Species of Rights’ (2001) 89 California Law Review 207, available at https://www.jstor.org/stable/3481176
  • For a comparison of Francione’s and Wise’s theories from an outsider perspective to animal law, focusing on their strategic potential, see: Douglas E Beloof, ‘Crime Victims’ Rights: Critical Concepts for Animal Rights’ (2001) 7 Animal Law 19, available at https://www.animallaw.info/article/crime-victims%C2%92-rights-critical-concepts-animal-rights
  • For a review of Kurki’s theory of personhood, and a rejoinder by Kurki debating the relevance of thin and thick rights in Francione’s and Wise’s theories, see: Raffael N Fasel, ‘Shaving Ockham: A Review of Visa A.J. Kurki’s “A Theory of Legal Personhood”’ (2021) 44 Revus, available at https://doi.org/10.4000/revus.6921 and Visa AJ Kurki, ‘On Legal Personhood: Rejoinders, Reflections and Restatements’ (2021) 44 Revus, available at https://doi.org/10.4000/revus.7425
  • For an analysis of four types of legal personification for animals through personhood, drawing on French legal theory, see: David Chauvet, ‘Four Kinds of Nonhuman Animal Legal Personification’ (2020) 8 Global Journal of Animal Law 1, available at https://ojs.abo.fi/ojs/index.php/gjal/article/view/1670
  • For an argument that animals can be personified as legal persons, and should be, to shift perceptions of animals as being intrinsically valuable, see: Jane Nosworthy, ‘The Koko Dilemma – A Challenge to Legal Personality’ (1998) 2 Southern Cross University Law Review 1, available at http://classic.austlii.edu.au/au/journals/SCULawRw/1998/2.html
  • For an argument that animals do have an intrinsic interest in liberty, see: Marc G Wilcox, ‘The Intrinsic Value of Liberty for Non-Human Animals’ (2021) 55 Journal of Value Inquiry 685, available at https://doi.org/10.1007/s10790-020-09762-1
  1. Conclusion
  • For an argument that animal protection legislation confers rights on animals, which addresses several themes from this chapter, see: Darren Sean Calley, ‘Human Duties, Animal Suffering, and Animal Rights: A Legal Reevaluation’ in Andrew Linzey and Clair Linzey (eds), The Palgrave Handbook of Practical Animal Ethics (1st ed. 2018, Palgrave Macmillan UK: Imprint: Palgrave Macmillan 2018), available at https://doi.org/10.1057/978-1-137-36671-9_24
  • For an argument that animals can be considered legal persons under any of four conceptions of legal personhood, which covers several themes from the chapter, see: Macarena Montes Franceschini, ‘Traditional Conceptions of the Legal Person and Nonhuman Animals’ (2022) 12 Animals 2590, available at https://pubmed.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/36230329/